Théberge v. Galerie d'Art du Petit Champlain Inc.

Théberge v. Galerie d'Art du Petit Champlain Inc.

Supreme Court of Canada

Hearing: October 11, 2001
Judgment: March 28, 2002
Full case name: Théberge v. Galerie d'Art du Petit Champlain Inc.
Citations: [2002] 2 S.C.R. 336, 2002 SCC 34
History: Appeal from the Quebec Court of Appeal, 9 C.P.R. (4th) 259
Ruling: Appeal allowed. Order of the Quebec Court of Appeal vacated.
Court membership

Chief Justice: Beverley McLachlin
Puisne Justices: Claire L'Heureux-Dubé, Charles Gonthier, Frank Iacobucci, John C. Major, Michel Bastarache, Ian Binnie, Louise Arbour, Louis LeBel

Reasons given

Majority by: Binnie J.
Joined by: McLachlin C.J. Iacobucci and Major JJ.
Dissent by: Gonthier J.
Joined by: L'Heureux-Dubé and LeBel JJ.

Théberge v. Galerie d'Art du Petit Champlain Inc. [2002] 2 S.C.R. 336, 2002 SCC 34 is one of the Supreme Court of Canada's leading cases on copyright law. This case interprets the meaning of "reproduction" within the Copyright Act of Canada, and touches on the moral rights to copyrighted material and how much control an author has over his work once it is in the hands of a third party.

Contents

Background

Galerie d'Art du Petit Champlain bought the rights to make a limited number of paper copies of Mr. Théberge's paintings in order to create posters from them. Through a chemical process the gallery was able to lift the ink off the paper and put it onto a canvas. This transferring destroyed the paper version in the process. The gallery then sold the paintings for a substantial premium over the cost of the paper posters.

Théberge had a bailiff seize the paintings as violations of his copyright and his moral rights. By the time the case reached the Supreme Court, Théberge had yet to proceed with his case on the merits.

Opinion of the Court

The issues before the court were whether transferring the work from paper to canvas violated the Copyright Act by creating an unauthorized reproduction, and to what extent does an artist have control over the reproduction of their work. The resolution of these issues would determine the pre-judgment authority the author has to seize the works.

Binnie J., with McLachlin C.J. Iacobucci, and Major JJ. concurring, held that there was no reproduction involved as no new copies were made. There was only the transfer of ink which is considered a modification rather than a copy. The Court found the artist's legitimate economic interests were not changed by the transferring of the ink from paper to canvas. It also found that if they considered the creation of the canvas as a "reproduction" despite the lack of multiplication, they would be reading in the American right of derivative works, a concept without statutory basis in Canadian copyright law.

The Court criticized the plaintiff for trying to make a moral argument where the issue is one of economics when there is a claim of copyright infringement as opposed to moral right infringement. In a claim of moral rights the plaintiff could have sued on the modification of the art, but no argument was made by the party. The Court also ruled that pre-judgment seizure is not available to an artist who claims a violation of his moral rights.

In the end the court felt that it should not put too much power in the hands of the artist over the purchaser of the art, as it would overly limit the ability of private property owners to do what they will with their possessions.

Purpose of Copyright

In reaching his conclusion, Binnie J. made several statements regarding the purpose and nature of Copyright law in which he characterized it as a balance between interests.

The Copyright Act is usually presented as a balance between promoting the public interest in the encouragement and dissemination of works of the arts and intellectu and obtainning a just reward for the creator (or, more accurately, to prevent someone other than the creator from appropriating whatever benefits may be generated).[1]

He characterizes the use of Copyright as a limited economic right:

The proper balance among these and other public policy objectives lies not only in recognizing the creator's rights but in giving due weight to their limited nature. In crassly economic terms it would be as inefficient to overcompensate artists and authors for the right of reproduction as it would be self-defeating to undercompensate them. Once an authorized copy of a work is sold to a member of the public, it is generally for the purchaser, not the author, to determine what happens to it.[2]

Significantly, as well, he acknowledges the need for a public domain:

Excessive control by holders of copyrights and other forms of intellectual property may unduly limit the ability of the public domain to incorporate and embellish creative innovation in the long-term interests of society as a whole, or create practical obstacles to proper utilization. This is reflected in the exceptions to copyright infringement enumerated in ss. 29 to 32.2, which seek to protect the public domain in traditional ways such as fair dealing for the purpose of criticism or review and to add new protections to reflect new technology, such as limited computer program reproduction and "ephemeral recordings" in connection with live performances.[3]

Dissent

L'Heureux-Dubé, Gonthier and LeBel JJ. (in dissent) took an artist-oriented approach. They interpreted the purpose of the copyright act as a means of protecting the rights of artists, and as such must take a broader interpretation of "reproduction". In their definition "reproduction" does not necessarily involve making additional copies, rather a "reproduction" was merely a "fixation". That is, a new physical structure or "production" of the work.

See also

References

  1. ^ para. 30
  2. ^ para. 31
  3. ^ para. 32

External links